From: mueckenh on

Daryl McCullough schrieb:

> mueckenh(a)rz.fh-augsburg.de says...
>
> >> >> > There is no bijective mapping f : |N --> M,
> >> >> > where M contains the set of all finite subsets of |N
> >> >> > and, in addition, the set K = {k e |N : k /e f(k)} of all natural
> >> >> > numbers k which are mapped on subsets not containing k.
>
> >Above I spelled out clearly that M contains the set of all finite
> >subsets of |N and one more set K. What is unclear?
>
> Okay, so M is not a fixed set, but is a function of f. So to make
> this precise, let's put in the functional dependence:
>
> K(f) = { k in N | k is not an element of f(k) }
> M(f) = { A in P(N) | A is finite, or A = K(f) }
>
> where P(N) means the set of all subsets of N.
>
> Then what you are saying is that
>
> forall f: N -> P(N),
> f is not a bijection between N and M(f)
>
> That's true. But that doesn't mean that M(f) is uncountable.

If it is proven impossible to set up a mapping between M and |N, then M
is uncountable.
That is the definition of uncountability. Cp. Cantor's diagonal proof:
There it is even possible to set up a bijektion between {numbers of the
list & diagonal number}, (after the diagonal number has been
constructed) and |N. Nevertheless uncountablilty is claimed.

> We can prove
>
> forall f: N -> P(N), exists g: N -> P(N)
> g is a bijection between N and M(f)

No, it is not, because M(f) is incomplete without K. But K does not
exist. The reason for its non-existence is not lacking number of
elements of |N but an impredicable definition. I only wanted to point
out that the same impradicability is the reason Hessenberg' s proof
(non-surjectivity of f: |N --> P(|N)) seems to hold. It does not. In
fact, it has nothing to do with any number of elements of any set.

Regards, WM

From: mueckenh on

Virgil schrieb:


> For any given f:|N --> M_f there is a
> h:M_f --> |N which is a bijection, and such an h is easy to constrruct.

No, it is not, because M_f is incomplete without K. But K does not
exist. The reason for its non-existence is not a lacking number of
elements of |N but an impredicable definition. I only wanted to point
out that the same impradicability is the reason why Hessenberg' s proof
(non-surjectivity of f: |N --> P(|N)) seems to hold. It does not. In
fact, it has nothing to do with any number of elements of any set.
>

> Now for any f: |N --> M_f, of all finite subsets of |N together with
> K = {k e |N : k /e f(k)} as members:
>
> (1) either K is finite, in which case
> G = M_f and h = g is a bijection between M_f and |N
>
> or
>
> (2) K is not finite, in which case
> we can define h so that h(K) = 0 and
> for x in G h(x) = g(x) + 1.
>
> Thus in any event, for every given f: |N --> M_f
> there is an easily constricted bijection between |N and M_f.

The element K of M does not exist.

If it is proven impossible to set up a mapping between M and |N, then M
is uncountable.
That is the definition of uncountability. Cp. Cantor's diagonal proof:
There it is even possible to set up a bijektion between {numbers of the
list & diagonal number}, (after the diagonal number has been
constructed) and |N. Nevertheless uncountablilty is claimed.

Your arguing would establish countability for {numbers of the list &
diagonal number}, because the diagonal number increases the set only by
1 element.

Regards, WM

From: Virgil on
In article <1150782120.872330.199120(a)c74g2000cwc.googlegroups.com>,
mueckenh(a)rz.fh-augsburg.de wrote:

> Daryl McCullough schrieb:
>
> > mueckenh(a)rz.fh-augsburg.de says...
> >
> > >> >> > There is no bijective mapping f : |N --> M,
> > >> >> > where M contains the set of all finite subsets of |N
> > >> >> > and, in addition, the set K = {k e |N : k /e f(k)} of all natural
> > >> >> > numbers k which are mapped on subsets not containing k.
> >
> > >Above I spelled out clearly that M contains the set of all finite
> > >subsets of |N and one more set K. What is unclear?
> >
> > Okay, so M is not a fixed set, but is a function of f. So to make
> > this precise, let's put in the functional dependence:
> >
> > K(f) = { k in N | k is not an element of f(k) }
> > M(f) = { A in P(N) | A is finite, or A = K(f) }
> >
> > where P(N) means the set of all subsets of N.
> >
> > Then what you are saying is that
> >
> > forall f: N -> P(N),
> > f is not a bijection between N and M(f)
> >
> > That's true. But that doesn't mean that M(f) is uncountable.
>
> If it is proven impossible to set up a mapping between M and |N, then M
> is uncountable.

But you have not proven it impossible, you merely argue that ONE
function between N and M(f) is not a bijection.



WE have some f: N --> P(N), which we know is not a surjection since
there is no n in N for which one can have f(n) = K(f).

But that does no mean that there is no surjection between M(f) and N.

In fact, given a function f for which K(f) exists, it is not difficult
to build a bijection between M(f) and N as follows:

For each S in M(F) define g: M(f) --> N by:
If K is finite then
if 0 e N
then g(S) = sum_{s e S} 2^s
else g(S) = sum_{s e S} 2^(s-1)
endif
else (K being infinite)
g(K) = the first natural
and
if 0 e N
then g(S) = sum_{s e S} 2^s+1
else g(S) = sum_{s e S} 2^(s-1)+1
endif
endif

In all these cases, g will be a bijection from M(f) to N.



>
> > We can prove
> >
> > forall f: N -> P(N), exists g: N -> P(N)
> > g is a bijection between N and M(f)
>
> No, it is not, because M(f) is incomplete without K. But K does not
> exist.

But you have not proven it never exists, and for some functions, f, it
Does exist.

For example, let f(n) = {} for all n, then
K = {k in N : not k e f(k) } = N.

So that for SOME functions f, f, K(f) exists.

The reason that Meucken's argument fails here is that there is no
necessity for the function f to be a surjection onto M(f).

The desired bijection can be established by an entirely different
function between M(f) and N, as shown above.







> The reason for its non-existence is not lacking number of
> elements of |N but an impredicable definition.

Wrong, as shown by a specific example above.
From: Virgil on
In article <1150782414.064700.253320(a)p79g2000cwp.googlegroups.com>,
mueckenh(a)rz.fh-augsburg.de wrote:

> Virgil schrieb:
>
>
> > For any given f:|N --> M_f there is a
> > h:M_f --> |N which is a bijection, and such an h is easy to constrruct.
>
> No, it is not, because M_f is incomplete without K. But K does not
> exist.


That requires proof, and is false in at least one case.
Let f(n) = {} for all n, then K_f is quite well defined.


> The reason for its non-existence is not a lacking number of
> elements of |N but an impredicable definition. I only wanted to point
> out that the same impradicability is the reason why Hessenberg' s proof
> (non-surjectivity of f: |N --> P(|N)) seems to hold. It does not. In
> fact, it has nothing to do with any number of elements of any set.
> >
>
> > Now for any f: |N --> M_f, of all finite subsets of |N together with
> > K = {k e |N : k /e f(k)} as members:
> >
> > (1) either K is finite, in which case
> > G = M_f and h = g is a bijection between M_f and |N
> >
> > or
> >
> > (2) K is not finite, in which case
> > we can define h so that h(K) = 0 and
> > for x in G h(x) = g(x) + 1.
> >
> > Thus in any event, for every given f: |N --> M_f
> > there is an easily constricted bijection between |N and M_f.
>
> The element K of M does not exist.

That requires proof, and is false in at least one case.
Let f(n) = {} for all n, then K_f is quite well defined, and equals N.
>
> If it is proven impossible to set up a mapping between M and |N, then M
> is uncountable.

Wrong!

If it is impossible to set up an injection from N to M_F or a surjection
from M_f to N, and the axiom of choice is assumed, only then is M_f
uncountable.

And if K does not exist, as Meucken asserts above, then neither does any
set which is required to have it as a member, so that no such set as M_f
nor any such function as f:N --> M_f exists either, and his whole
argument collapses.
From: Rupert on

mueckenh(a)rz.fh-augsburg.de wrote:
> Rupert schrieb:
>
> > mueckenh(a)rz.fh-augsburg.de wrote:
> > > An uncountable countable set
> > >
> > > There is no bijective mapping f : |N --> M,
> > > where M contains the set of all finite subsets of |N
> > > and, in addition, the set K = {k e |N : k /e f(k)} of all natural
> > > numbers k which are mapped on subsets not containing k.
> > >
> >
> > You're using the notation "f" in two ways.
>
> No.

Yep. In one of the occurrences it occurs preceded by a universal
quantifier, in the other it occurs as a constant symbol.

>
> > First you're denying that a
> > function f with certain properties exists, then you're defining M in
> > terms of some fixed function f,
>
> f is not fixed by any prescription.
>

It doesn't make sense to talk about the set K={k e |N: k /e f(k)} unles
you've specified what f is.

> > which it's not clear what it is. Use a
> > different letter for the two things, and the define the function
>
> f is not restricted by any definition. Any mapping f: |N --> M is
> allowed.
>

So you mean M is the set of all finite subsets of |N, together with all
sets of the form K={k e |N: k /e f(k)}, where f ranges over all
possible mappings |N->P(|N)? That set is clearly uncountable. There is
no problem there.

> > in
> > terms of which you're defining M.
>
> Let p and q be two natural numbers and let sqrt(2) = p/q.
>
> Regards, WM

First  |  Prev  |  Next  |  Last
Pages: 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15
Prev: integral problem
Next: Prime numbers